A popular trope these days depicts faith and
religion as opposed to science. The logic behind this is simple –
science is based on testability, reproducibility, and acting based on
evidence. Religion by it's nature is considered to require actions
based on faith, rather than evidence, and many religious claims are
inherently untestable, or at least such tests as may be argued to be
possible have factors that make such testing not reproducible; in
terms of philosophy or science, the claims are unfalsifiable.
Anti-religion advocates also often point to
religious persecution of scientists, as in the case of Galileo
Galilei, or of religious authorities resisting the adoption or
teaching of science, as in the case of evolution (for some time) or
the attempts to have schools teach intelligent design as science.
However, it is also true that many great scientists have been
religious, such as the (Quaker) astronomer Arthur Stanley Eddington,
and the polymath Blaise Pascal. There are also cases of cultures and
times where religion, even relatively authoritarian religion, has
been a dominant feature of life, yet sciences have flourished –
most notably the Islamic Golden Age.
The debate about whether religion in general is
compatible with science will carry on in many places, especially
online forums and blogs, for a long time yet. In this post, I will be
addressing specifically the underlying assertion that faith stands
opposed to reason and evidence, and applying specifically my own
non-theist Quaker approach to faith to look at the implications.
It is true that religious claims are generally
unfalsifiable, and thus not amenable to scientific analysis. Quakers
love, in line with our general habit of using old phrases, to say
that we know what we know, in terms of religion, “experimentally”.
We must remember, however, that this word was not used, by early
Friends, in its modern sense. In modern English, we might say
“experientially”, instead. This is because of a shift in the word
“experiment” to take on specifically scientific connotations, as
the idea of scientific method became more prominent and everyday;
formerly, it meant much the same as “experience”, and thus
knowing something experimentally meant knowing it from your own
observations without necessarily implying that they were in any way
scientific.
Each Quaker, of an unprogrammed tradition, has
experienced Meeting for Worship and, one would hope, has experienced
something profound in that silence. We thus, each of us, know that
there is that something to be experienced – though we may have
different ideas about what it is. Thus, by Quaker tradition, we say
we “know experimentally” that there is something to be found in
silent worship. By this, we should not mean that we think our
observation has empirically proved the existence of something; no
matter how many people experience it, we cannot say, in the sense
used in discussing science, that it is a reproducible observation.
This is because it cannot be reproduced by an arbitrary person
regardless of their inclinations or beliefs – we will freely say
that it takes a certain metaphorical leap of faith to engage in
worship, a seeking, and that it won't always be found. This is
especially true for the novice. Thus we cannot have an arbitrary
experimenter come and reproduce the findings, thus it is not
reproducible. It is also purely qualitative, which tends to be less
amenable to scientific measurement, but is not an inherent barrier.
Our statement is also not falsifiable, because it
is a subjective experience. No-one could do anything to demonstrate
that we hadn't really experienced what we claim to experience. This
is related to the matter of reproducibility; if we asserted that
everyone who followed some simple formula, entirely of
externally-verifiable steps, would have a certain experience, that
would be somewhat falsifiable. People would be able to take those
steps, have others verify that they had followed those steps
precisely, and report whether or not they had the experience. The
only thing limiting the falsifiability is the subjective nature of
the experience – they could lie about not experiencing it.
So it is that one of the most key religious truths
of Quakers, one of the most practically important, is clearly not a
matter that can be subjected to scientific enquiry. This is, of
course, no criticism of Quaker beliefs; as a practising Quaker, who
will be found in Meeting for Worship every week with only rare
exceptions, it would be very strange if I were criticising it. There
is something in our worship, of that I am sure. However, I cannot
expect my certainty to sway other people, because it is entirely
subjective. We could get into epistemological classifications of
different sorts of knowledge – which would in turn depend on
epistemological assumptions that differ between different paradigms
and approaches – but the key differentiation here is what I will
simply call subjective and objective knowledge (my usage may agree
with that of some philosophers; it certainly does not agree with the
usage of all, because philosophical uses of the terms is not entirely
consistent). In both cases, “knowledge” implies certainty, but
for matters of subjective knowledge, one does not expect that
certainty to mean anything to another person. For objective
knowledge, the same will apply to anyone and everyone, and can be
objectively demonstrated. Thus it is objective knowledge that
electricity works, that moving bodies follow Newton's laws (at least
in the Newtonian limit – but don't worry about that, it's a physics
thing), even that chemicals have certain properties in relation to
one another. These things can all be demonstrated experimentally, not
just experienced. Anyone mixing chemical A with chemical B in set of
conditions C will get the same result, or near enough within
reasonable experimental error; while a religious experience may give
one a solid certainty about religious matters, there is not the same
ability to demonstrate it to absolutely anyone.
This distinction of types of knowledge, categories
of certainty, may seem less important to those with a perspective of
faith that is not universalist and pluralist. With this idea of
subjective knowledge, it is possible that I know one thing, and
another person knows, with the same certainty, something that utterly
contradicts my knowledge. With the idea of subjective knowledge,
there is no contradiction here – there is no logical requirement
that one of us be wrong. This doesn't just apply to religion; in the
absence of absolutely reliable evidence (such as audio and video
recordings), this is also true of “what was said in a
conversation”; human memory isn't a tape recorder, we encode the
things we remember, and when we decode them we will find that two
people, both considered reliable witnesses, will have ended up with
different results from that encoding–decoding process. If a
recording shows that one of them has a more accurate recollection
than the other, this is usually simply a matter of luck, rather than
one person being more wrong than the other – or more mendacious.
Subjective knowledge is related to an acceptance of fallibility, yet
need not mean we do not feel genuine certainty about these things
that we know.
For someone whose religious perspective is
exclusive, however, the idea of subjective knowledge is harder to
grasp. They may be utterly certain over some matter of religion, and
thus anyone whose knowledge is different to them does not really have
knowledge – they have errors. They are wrong. But any scientist who
is also strongly religious absolutely must accept the idea of
subjective knowledge, or else live with significant cognitive
dissonance – a feat humans have repeatedly demonstrated they are
frequently capable of. This is because there is such a significant
difference in the quality of scientific knowledge and religious
knowledge, the only way to avoid the cognitive dissonance is to
confront it and construct an understanding similar to the one I have
outlined. I would imagine that this makes religious scientists more
likely to tend to the less-dogmatic end of the religious world,
especially when they live in a religiously pluralistic society –
exposing them to a wider range of religious truths. I have, however,
no data to base such a supposition on; it simply flows from reason,
which is a very poor way to make conclusions about the world.
It is worth a quick digression at this point to
consider the differences between the physical or natural sciences
(biology, chemistry, physics etc.), the social sciences (sociology,
at least some elements of psychology, and various specialist areas
like educational research), and other numerate disciplines (such as
mathematics or computer science). The principles of experimentation
and objective knowledge are most well-defined in the natural
sciences, as they are full of things that can be studied in properly
constructed experiments that reasonably control or eliminate
potential confounding factors; the inability to do so often in social
sciences leads to a much larger proportion of subjective knowledge
propagating and competing in such disciplines (I say this speaking as
one trained and experienced in social science), and as such the meat
of this post is less applicable to them – though not completely
inapplicable. Mathematics is a rather special case. Speaking as one
trained in mathematics, a lot of laypeople don't realise the extent
to which mathematics is a constructed discipline. The fact it leads
to real-world results of some reliability confuses many into thinking
that it is a science, but really it is a very specialised branch of
philosophy that happens to have been found to be of more reliable
everyday use than most of the rest of philosophy put together. As a
constructed discipline, it is possible to absolutely demonstrate
certain things as true – but only given the fundamental axioms of
the area you are working in. Computer science, speaking as one
trained in the discipline, is a weird mishmash of different sorts of
science; very occasionally there's a bit of physical science, but
it's mostly elements of constructed discipline mixed with social
science.
Those who are not scientists, however, are far
less likely to be confronted with the inherent difference in these
sorts of knowledge. This is because they acquire knowledge about
scientific things in largely the same way they acquire knowledge
about religious things; what is, to human society as a whole,
objective knowledge is, to them, subjective knowledge. They could
reasonably be said to have objective knowledge about a few things
they have seen experimentally demonstrated – or been able to try
for themselves – in science lessons, but otherwise their knowledge
of science comes from books, and from what a person they are expected
to trust tells them (or from popular media, including fiction,
leading to unfortunate results far too often). This is, of course,
much the same as where their religious knowledge comes from.
The same is true to a scientist, to a certain
extent. It has been a long time since it's been plausible for a
single person, over the course of an education and a working life, to
witness or participate in experiments that cover all known science.
Nowadays, that would not only take an implausible amount of time, but
it would take a phenomenal amount of money; experiments demonstrating
any sort of recently discovered physical science – by which we're
looking at around 100 years, at least – tend to be expensive,
either in terms of materials and equipment, or because they require
some sort of unusual circumstance, like a total solar eclipse. At
some point, you have to trust those who have performed the
experiment. This is made easier by the fact that, for some principle
to make its way to the scientific canon, it must be demonstrated by
repeated results, from different experimenters. It is subject to
significant scrutiny from the community of the discipline in
question, with mostly good-natured attempts to pull down one
another's work. This is not done out of enmity (at least, not all the
time), but because it is necessary that the work must be harrowed in
order to bear fruit. This is not, in most religious communities, how
religious thought is treated.
It is because the religious scientist can separate
these sorts of knowledge that they can be faithful to both pursuits.
I do not say all can do it; I'm sure many live with cognitive
dissonance, especially those occasional scientists who pursue science
professionally while also advocating the teaching of intelligent
design as part of a science curriculum. Some in the atheist/sceptic
community, seeming to almost deify science, insist on the idea of
scientific, objective knowledge as a gold standard, and thus
criticise religion, all religion, for its non-falsifiability. Few of
them extend this to the arts, however; they are happy with the idea
of “I know it when I see it” in artistic appreciation, implicitly
accepting the idea of subjective knowledge as valid in such a
context, especially given the great divergence of opinions as to when
a TV show, or play, or painting or poem is good. It is, perhaps, only
the fact that some religious people put forth their beliefs as
objectively correct that leads the sceptic community to have such
negativity towards religion in general.
Of course, the religion that intrudes most on the
general awareness is the religion that holds itself out as
objectively true – especially because such beliefs are more likely
to lead to proselytism, to standing up in public proclaiming those
beliefs and calling on others to join you in them. Perhaps if the
religious positions people saw publicly did not so often tend to the
absolute, it would be harder to assume that such things are inherent
in religion itself. Perhaps if groups like the Unitarians (or
Unitarian Universalists, in North America) and liberal Quakers were
more visible, more heard from – and on religious subjects, rather
than on social issues – people would be more likely to realise that
there are religions that embrace the idea of subjective knowledge,
and more people would grow to understand the concept, even if they
never use the term. More people understanding epistemology would be a
good thing in itself, but subtly breaking down the perceived
adversarial relationship between science and religion, replacing it
with an understanding of the difference in approach and applicable
domains, would be a marvellous result, much to be desired.
~ ~ ~ ~ ~
Did you enjoy this post, or find it interesting, informative or stimulating? Do you want to keep seeing more of these posts? Please consider contributing to my Patreon. More information is available in the post announcing my use of Patreon.
Did you enjoy this post, or find it interesting, informative or stimulating? Do you want to keep seeing more of these posts? Please consider contributing to my Patreon. More information is available in the post announcing my use of Patreon.